Enhancing our Grasp of Complex
Arguments
Paul Monk and Tim van Gelder
Austhink
www.austhink.org
This paper was presented by Paul
Monk as a plenary address to the
2004 Fenner
Conference on the Environment, Australian Academy of Science,
Canberra, 24 May 2004
For the
next two days, a series of individuals are going to address you, all
approaching the matter of population and environment in 21st
century Australia from different angles. How much of what they say will you
retain? How clearly? How much overlap will there be between what any two of
you retain, not to mention the whole gathering? How will you know? How much
congruence will there be between the questions you ask of the different
speakers? How cogent will their answers be? How will we be clear about the
significance of their answers? What consensus, if any, will be generated by
the conference? To what extent will such consensus be justified? How will we
know? These are all questions about the cognitive process of
deliberating. It is this process, not the substantive matter in hand, that I
will address this morning.
My main contention is
simple. Using a technique called argument mapping, we can structure,
communicate and correct arguments of any degree of complexity with a clarity
and efficiency simply unavailable using other means. If we use the technique
in a deliberative process, we can govern the deliberation, constrain it from
straying off course, target our use of evidence, specify our disagreements,
and capture the whole process with an ease and rigour significantly greater
than are available using standard cognitive processes.
We are a
accustomed to behave as if, where there is a lot of earnest talk and a great
accumulation of stuff written or printed on paper, some serious thinking
must be going on. This is, in an important sense, an illusion. The standard
processes we use to run conferences or conduct other forms of deliberation
are highly inefficient and seldom enhance either shared clarity or justified
consensus. Why? Because we stumble around in a fog of verbiage, missing much
of what is said, asking a scattering of uncoordinated questions, making
misinferences and misassociations, grabbing only bits and pieces of
arguments and clinging to our own for all we are worth, if only as flotsam
that will keep us afloat in the swirling currents of the great river of argy
bargy. We lack agreed and effective processes for doing better than this. We
just do what is customary and write off the ineffectiveness of it all. Isn’t
that so?
But why
is it so? Because we are dealing with cognitive challenges orders of
complexity more demanding than our natural faculties and ancient ways of
communicating can adequately cope with. We are, after all, biological
beings, whose brains evolved, over aeons, to cope with an overwhelmingly
sensory environment - visual, tactile, auditory, olfactory. Language emerged
very late as a means of more fluidly sharing information and emotion. With
it, there emerged a latent cognitive capacity for symbolic thinking. It is
this capacity which enabled our species to become technologically and
graphically creative. That is a cumulative process, which feeds on itself.
It generated the invention of writing, from only 5,000 years ago, followed
by more and more advanced systems of record keeping and reasoning based on
writing.
Most of
the thinking we now do cannot be done without being fed through the loop of
externally stored records, writing processes and mental cues linked to such
records and processes. Using these records and processes, over just a few
millennia, we have accomplished altogether extraordinary things. Yet our
biological brains have not changed appreciably in that time. What is the
consequence of this? That the demands made on our brains have become ever
more varied and complex, while their default capacities and proclivities
have remained unchanged. This has all manner of implications, but we often
behave, in deliberative processes, as though we were almost wholly
unconscious of such implications.
In other
words, we more or less blunder around in the external record system and
behave in argument as if we were still sensory beings hunting and gathering
in the uncomplicated, primeval sensory world. We conduct complex arguments
as if a combination of holistic apprehension, intuitive judgment and natural
language were sufficient for handling them. None of us, I think, would
consciously make that claim. We do what we do by tradition and by default,
not because we have thought through why we do it, how it works and whether
it serves us well. Because we have, all of us, read a lot, argued a lot and
consider ourselves - if not those we disagree with - to be more or less
rational beings, we hold these debates in ways barely distinguishable from
the way tribal moots were held millennia ago. We do so because it is not
obvious how we can do much better.
These are
large claims to make and it is probably not clear what I am saying here, if
only because what I am saying is true! Let me, therefore, illustrate my
point in a simple and playful way. Our brains have remarkable capacities for
visual apprehension, astonishing capacities for assimilating information
into routines of an autonomic kind and into long term associative memory,
but they have very limited working memory. This has direct
implications for any task which requires holding more than a very few items
of information in working memory at one time. Any but the most basic
thinking task fits this description.
To
illustrate this, let’s run a few variations on a simple game. Take a piece
of paper and, turning to the person next to you, play out a game of noughts
and crosses (tic tac toe). Easy, right? Now, let’s move to stage two.
This time, play a game of noughts and crosses without using a board.
Just hold the grid in your mind’s eye and talk one another through the game.
Harder, right? Doable, but you have to concentrate a lot more, because what
was held for you, fixed in place on an external record before, now had to be
held in place in your own working memory.
Now,
consider playing noughts and crosses on a 4 x 4 grid, but again without the
board. This stretches working memory capacity beyond its ordinary limits.
What is a straight forward enough cognitive task, when external records are
in use, becomes an extremely challenging task when we must rely on the
unassisted brain. Of course, to some extent, we can train our brains to do
complex tasks, just as we can train our bodies to perform remarkable feats
of athleticism or endurance. But I invite you to reflect for a moment on the
implications of what you have just experienced for the incomparably more
complex cognitive task of debating such issues as we are gathered here to
discuss.
Consider
that, in the noughts and crosses game, you have to keep the whole grid in
mind throughout the game. If part of it drops out, or if you forget where
you or your opponent have placed a marker, you put your game in jeopardy. If
this is so, why do we try to play the game of argument, where there are
incomparably more pieces than in a 4 x 4 noughts and crosses grid, as if we
have every chance of playing it well? I suggest that the answer is, at least
in part, that we do so because we have only a hazy notion of what we are
actually trying to accomplish. In other words, the rules of the game are so
ill-defined that all sorts of cognitive chaos gets accepted, as if it was
sound gamesmanship.
Who among
us would suggest that it made any sense at all to play a gigantic game of
noughts and crosses without the use of an external record, or with only bits
of it visible at any given time? Yet isn’t this the way we conduct
conferences, meetings and other deliberative processes? The consequence is
that move and counter move are made while large parts of the board or game
sheet light up or fade out. Moves become confused, repetitive, uncertain,
controverted. Our powers of concentration are severely taxed, we tend to
become frustrated, exhausted and skeptical of the reasoning abilities of
others. Very often, the game is declared over without any demonstrable end
game having been reached.
This
problem of limited working memory capacity is accentuated by three
additional factors: cognitive blind spots and biases, the methods we
actually use to record and communicate arguments, and the fact that
different disciplines create their own idiolects, their own peculiar jargon
and languages of proof, that cut them off from one another. All these
factors impede both the progress of inquiry, in general, and collaborative
inquiry across disciplines, in particular. All of them I suggest, clearly
operate in the prolonged and complex debate over population policy and
environmental futures in this country.
Consider
first the cognitive blind spots and biases, which distort the way we process
even what information we grasp. There is quite a list of these blind spots
and biases, but let me mention only two of the most evident and endemic:
belief preservation and confirmation bias. Belief preservation is the
automatic human tendency, once having formed a strong opinion, to cling to
it not only while available evidence might appear to support it, but even
when a good deal of evidence begins to suggest it is questionable, if not
downright false. It involves the default tendency to ignore, deny, devalue
or dismiss such evidence.
Confirmation bias is the tendency to seek information that will confirm a
belief, a hypothesis or an intuition, rather than trying to test or falsify
them. We are all prone to these tendencies. Mentioning them is not to imply
that they are why one side or another in the population debate is wrong.
Rather, it is to intended to encourage all participants in the debate to
open their opinions up to critical examination and allow that they could be
in error in some fundamental way. For nothing is more striking to an
observer of the debate than the manner in which passionate opinions are
polemically defended by environmentalists, economists, physical
scientists, business people and policy makers, rather than conceded to be
uncertain and open to critical examination.
To this
end, we need something other than a free-flowing argy bargy, or even the
giving of speeches and the circulation of manuscripts - the standard methods
we use to record and communicate arguments. I do not, of course, mean to
suggest that these methods are hopelessly flawed. Their accomplishments,
over the past ten millennia and especially over the past few centuries, have
been astonishing. I do, however, suggest that they have more serious
limitations, from the point of view of cognitive process, than is ordinarily
understood - and that we can do better. Since we seem to have a greater need
than ever to be able to generate rational consensus and to be able to sift
truth from error, anything that improves the way we record and communicate
arguments must be of benefit.
A
third reason why standard means of doing deliberation are
inefficient is the fact that different disciplines create their own
idiolects, their own peculiar jargon and languages of proof that cut them
off from one another. The most notorious kinds of idiolect of this nature
are, by common agreement, the arcane jargons developed, during the past half
century or so, by various, mostly French, schools of philosophy. The
problem, however, is not confined to those intellectual impostures so
memorably parodied by Alan Sokal in 1996, in his long article in Social
Text, ‘Transgressing the Boundaries: Toward a Transformative
Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity’. It extends across far more reputable
fields, because we lack a common language of good reasoning.
I am
referring here to informal reasoning, not to mathematical or purely logical
reasoning. It seems difficult for economists and historians, physicists and
biologists, ecologists and accountants to engage in clear and effective
intellectual exchange; or more difficult more often than we might prefer. I
suggest that one reason for this is that they do not have the means, for the
most part, to make themselves clear to one another. For example, when
Paul Krugman first took to writing short essays on economics for a general
readership, he did so, by his own account, because too many economists were
failing to communicate their reasoning to the non-specialist public.
He did not mean simply the under-educated. He meant all those not
specifically trained in mathematical economics.
I’m
saying that basic, standard cognitive processes we use to conduct
deliberative argumentation are inefficient because, as human beings, we have
limited working memory, and, therefore, lose the thread all too easily; are
given to default biases such as belief preservation and confirmation bias,
which compound the memory problem; use methods of recording and
communicating argument that systematically obscure our reasoning; and,
across disciplines, do not use the same methods for conducting inquiry,
discussing reasons or setting out cases.
I should
qualify this summary by stressing that, as much as anyone, I appreciate the
depth of scholarship and the careful thinking that goes into the best books
and papers. And I often enjoy the stimulus of conferences such as this, with
the opportunity they afford to hear and meet a variety of specialists and a
range of opinions. Please don’t misunderstand me, therefore, when I speak of
the deficiencies of our standard procedures. When I read, for example, Joel
Cohen’s How Many People Can the Earth Support?, or Mancur Olson’s
Power and Prosperity, or Andrew Parker’s In the Blink of an Eye,
to choose three tomes somewhat at random, I am enormously impressed.
My
suggestion, however, is that even in the case of tomes of that calibre, we
have to do a great deal of work to distill what, exactly, their argument is
on any given point; to say nothing of where such an argument clashes with
the arguments of others and precisely why one or another is mistaken. When
reading, when taking notes, when seeking to analyse such arguments or
communicate them to others, we have to decode them. Because of the
means used to encode them in the first place, this is very hard work. Why
need it be so? Just because the world is complex and reasoning itself
irreducibly difficult? Actually, no. This is my core message.
To
illustrate this in a simple and accessible way, let’s do another little
exercise. Here is a prose description of an area of London.
Pentonville Road runs from east to west, then turns into City Road,
which comes to a T-junction where East Road meet Moorgate City Road.
Running roughly south from Pentonville Road is first Gray’s Inn Road and
then King’s Cross Road, which turns into Farringdon Road after the
intersection with Clerkenwell Road. Where Pentonville Road turns into City
Road, St. John’s Street runs south. As you go along City Road, you come to
Goswell Road (which turns into Aldersgate Street) and Bunhill Row running
south. As you go down Gray’s Inn Road, the first intersection is with
Guildford Street, which continues to a T-junction with King’s Cross Road.
The next intersection, as you continue down Gray’s Inn Road, is with
Theobald’s Rd, which at that point turns into Clerkenwell Road, though you
could veer of NE along Rosebery Avenue which crosses King’s Cross Road
before it joins St. John’s Street near the junction of Pentonville Road
and City road. Gray’s Inn Road terminates at High Holborn, a major E-W
road which, as you go east, turns into Newgate Street and then Cheapside.
St. Paul’s Cathedral is between Newgate Street and Fleet Street, which
runs roughly parallel to Newgate. Southhampton Row goes south intersecting
with Guildford Street, Theobald’s Road and High Holborn, where it becomes
Kingsway, which continues south to a T-junction with the curve of Aldwych,
which begins and ends on Fleet Street. From Roseberry Road you can head
east along Lever Street, which crosses St. John’s Street and Goswell Road
before finishing at Bunhill Row where it meets City Road. Heading south
down St. John’s Road, you cross Lever Street and then Clerkenwell Road.
Goswell Road also crosses Lever Street and Clerkenwell Road (which at that
point becomes Old Street). Goswell Road becomes Aldersgate Street. Hatton
Garden goes between Clerkenwell Road and High Holborn. Streets running
south from High Holborn are Kingsway, Chancery Lane and Farringdon Road.
Chancery Lane is a short street finishing at Fleet Street. Fleet Street
ends at a large intersection just east of St. Paul’s. Aldersgate Street
continues past London Museum (which is at the corner of Alsdersgate and
London Wall) down to Newgate Street. Beech Street runs E from Aldersgate,
turning into Chiswell Street before it meets City Road. East Road runs
south, past the intersection of City Road, over Old Street and London
Wall, where it becomes Moorgate Street.
Those of
you who are fairly familiar with London may know your way around this part
of it. It’s the area surrounding St Paul’s Cathedral and the London Museum.
Now, please tell me, based on the information provided here: How does one
get from St Paul’s Cathedral to London Museum? The information is all
there. What makes it difficult to answer the question? You could figure it
out, given enough time, but you are, surely, both a little frustrated at the
unexpected difficulty of the task and puzzled at why I would present the
information to you in this form.
Why not
in this form?

This is,
of course, a map. Referring to it, we can use visual cues of color, line and
spatial relations to pick almost instantly how to get from St Paul’s
Cathedral to London Museum. That’s why we use maps. It would not occur to
any of us, unless we had no other choice, to try getting around a city
without a street map, simply relying on the verbal directions of its
inhabitants and our own working memory; to say nothing of relying on some
gargantuan directory in prose. Just imagine it!
Yet time
was when the first of these is pretty much what everyone did. Good, reliable
maps - and consequent ease of navigation and motoring - are modern
inventions. It is worth recalling, in this context, that, in the words of
Paul Binder, from his book Imagined Corners: Exploring the World’s First
Atlas,
“The most successful book of the entire sixteenth
century - the first century to open with the printed book as a fact of
Western life - was Theatrum orbis terrarum (Theatre of the
Countries of the World). It did something no previous book had done.
Here was the world itself, with its many component parts, and it was shown
to be both a place of extraordinary varieties and a singular whole. The
Theatrum, published in Antwerp on 20 May 1570, was the world’s
first-ever atlas.”
Since the
Theatrum was published, mapping has taken giant strides, but let’s
register what it was about this first world atlas that so impressed people
in the late sixteenth century. It was not simply a book of maps. Being an
atlas, it was a book in which all the maps cohered with one another - in
scale, symbols, names, lettering, figures - so that, in Binder’s words,
“there is a rationalized consistency throughout the book enabling us to
compare like with like - large country with large country, smaller island
with smaller island - while seeing them all as constituents of the same one
world.” One could see the whole and the part laid out with rational
consistency and move from the part to the whole with ease. That’s what the
Theatrum made possible that had not been possible before.
Now,
while consideration of the history of maps and atlases might lead on to
thoughts about the intensive colonization and exploitation of the whole
planet by our kind, I want to take the technology of mapping in a different
direction, as you will have guessed. Consider, in juxtaposition with the
prose description of the area of London around St Paul’s Cathedral and
London Museum, a standard opinion piece from a daily newspaper, dating back
about fifteen months.
Coalition of the Willing? Make That War Criminals is an argument
presented in prose. It was written by, or at least signed by, 43 Australian
international lawyers, before the war against Saddam Hussein began last
year.
There is
nothing unusual about this piece of writing as an opinion piece, or as a
piece of argument in prose. Its main contention is that, if the coalition of
the willing go to war, they will be war criminals by definition, because the
war will be illegal under international law. Now, consider three questions.
First, at the top level, how many distinct arguments do they provide for
their main point? That is to say, how many main lines of argument do they
have to back it up? Second, do they support all of these primary arguments
with further evidence? Third, do they countenance any objections to their
argument and rebut them?
Without
reading the text, you can’t answer these questions. I promise you, though,
that doing so would take more minutes than I have left in which to speak.
And, at the end of that time, you would still be discussing with me or one
another what the answers to my questions are and why. Here is a different
way to present such an argument: an argument map.
Click
on the thumbnail to view a full-sized image of this argument map.
|
Let me
briefly and simply explain its design principles. There is a proposition in
play, the chief contention. That goes in the white box. Supporting claims
are colour coded green and objections red. The claims are not in
linear sequence, as in the prose version, but are arranged in a pyramidal
hierarchy, so that their evidential and logical relationships are instantly
apparent.
Now, let
me repeat my questions. At the top level, how many distinct arguments
do they provide for their main point? [Three]. Do they support all of these
primary arguments with further evidence? [Yes]. Do they countenance any
objections to their argument and rebut them? [Yes, there is one objection
and it is rebutted on two grounds, each of which is supported by evidence].
Note that
you were all able to see these characteristics and effortlessly answer my
questions about the structure of the argument, because of its visuo-spatial
design, in contrast with the abstract, linear, non-colour coded version of
the argument in prose. There are at least seven reasons why this mapping of
the argument, or of any argument, confers cognitive advantages that prose
lacks.
First, it
makes explicit logical relationships that the linearity and abstractness of
prose cannot help but obscure. And I am referring here even to good prose,
carefully drafted, not merely to that sludge we all too frequently encounter
and, let’s be brutally frank, all too often write.
Second,
the map offers an instant and effortless scannability of the overall
structure of the argument, which you simply cannot derive from prose. You
found this the moment I asked you those three basic questions about the
structural characteristics of the War Criminals opinion piece. Just think of
the advantages this would confer, if it was to become standard practice, on
the reviewing of research papers, university essays, doctoral dissertations,
policy proposals, intelligence analyses. It simply saves time and effort,
which we are accustomed to expending, in trying to figure out what argument
a piece of prose presents.
Third,
there is an ease of movement from the detail to the overview that is far
more difficult in the case of prose. Just because the evidential and logical
relationships between propositions are visually explicit, one can move back
and forward between them rapidly, without the risk of misplacing,
overlooking or confusing claims, as chronically happens in critically
analyzing even relatively simple pieces of prose argumentation.
Fourth,
there are unambiguous visual clues as to the significance that particular
details have, due to the hierarchical ordering of the structure, the colour-coding
of the individual boxes and the inferential relations between boxes. Whereas
standard discussion or prose entails prolonged efforts to establish the
precise significance of details, in a map this is far more readily apparent,
with the consequence that we can much more rapidly zero in on the accuracy
of the detail, or the cogency of an inference from it.
Fifth, a
map offers a visual clarity as to the limits of a debate, whereas prose
obscures these limits or labours to spell them out. It is, for example,
instantly apparent, as we saw, in the map of the War Criminals argument,
that in one line of argument they had canvassed, and then rebutted, an
objection to their reasoning. Though
you won’t be able to read it from where you sit, it is also readily apparent
that the four reasons offered in support of the contention that war would
cause excessive loss of life or injury to civilians, in relation to the
overall military advantage anticipated, consist of three unsubstantiated
allegations and a strange non sequitur.
Sixth,
the cognitive burden imposed on us by the task of analyzing a piece of prose
is drastically reduced in the case of a map, for the same reasons that it is
reduced in moving from a prose description of London to a map. We can see
and move around the landscape and get down to the real work so much more
quickly, because we do not have to decode the prose. We don’t have to
assemble a representation of it in working memory. Given, as we have seen,
that working memory is so limited, this is no mean advantage.
Seventh,
for any given proposition, all claims are integrated into a single
structure, instead of consisting of various component parts, which then have
to be assembled by whoever happens to be trying to comprehend the argument
in question. Considering how prone we are to be swayed by salient details
and forgetful of many details, due to the combined effects of limited
working memory capacity, confirmation bias and belief preservation, this has
decided advantages in communicating complex argument.
This is a
lot to claim, a lot to digest, but consider that it is all visually apparent
in the very simple exercises we have shared. Let’s now revisit the standard
deliberative practices to which I made such critical reference earlier in my
speech. This, also, is visual and will bring many experiences to mind. What
do we do, when we are trying to nut something out? We sit and contemplate,
like Rodin’s penseur, or Archimedes in his bath, holding a mental
representation of a puzzle in our minds and trying to focus on important
aspects of it in order to get a breakthrough insight. Occasionally, this may
work, as it appears to have done in the case of Archimedes. But it is seldom
effective on its own.
More
commonly, we refer to the external record system, in the form of libraries
and databases. We avail ourselves, with greater or lesser facility, of the
notational tools necessary to work through the external record system. We
confer with others around tables, we debate across desks, we hold forth in
public assemblies and, perhaps, field questions. Very often we feel
overwhelmed by the complexity of the task and baffled even by the tools we
use to try to work things out.
But let’s
focus on the single most familiar practice in the processing of
deliberation, ever since the invention of writing: writing things down, or
up, as we sometimes phrase it. We tend to take writing so much for granted
now that we don’t reflect sufficiently on the fact that it is a kind of
secret code. To decipher what writing is saying requires that we interpret
the symbols. This becomes immediately apparent when we are confronted with a
foreign language, but we forget we are doing it when we are reading our own
language.
Now
consider that, when we are reading and analyzing an argument in
prose, we have to decode not simply the symbols and the meaning of the
words, but the reasoning that is being represented. What has to
happen here is that someone has to think up an argument, encode it in prose
and pass it to someone else, who then has to accurately decode it.
The emphasis here is on the word accurately. It is readily
demonstrable that, in fact, the argument suffers not only in formulation but
in transmission and decoding. Put bluntly, writing - in all its standard
forms - is simply a difficult medium for encoding and communicating
arguments.
The
consequence is that, more often than not, reasoning in prose is both poor
and poorly communicated. But even where it is reasonably sound, much of it
remains obscure to the reader. Commonly, however, argument is just poorly
structured and therefore poorly communicated. A central reason for
this is that the medium of prose does not lend itself to the clear
structuring or communication of reasoning. The wonderful Larson Far Side
cartoon The Boneless Chicken Ranch captures the point at issue. Such
poorly encoded and communicated arguments are what might be called Boneless
Chicken - plenty of flesh, but no skeleton, so they ain’t going anywhere
much.
I submit
that this is a dismal state of affairs at a time when, more than ever in the
past, we rely on the rapid and accurate communication of analysis and
argument. This is what Robert Reich was driving at, a decade ago, when he
described the knowledge economy as one in which
“The intellectual equipment needed for the
job of the future is an ability to define problems, quickly assimilate
relevant data, conceptualise and reorganise the information, make
deductive and inductive leaps with it, ask hard questions about it,
discuss findings with colleagues, work collaboratively to find solutions
and then convince others.”
We are admonished, from time
to time, to let the force be with us in this regard, to trust our gut, to
work on our intuitions, to not suffer paralysis by analysis and so on. But
these are superficial and even dangerous maxims. They are responses to the
sense of being overwhelmed by the complexity of the cognitive tasks that our
immense system of knowledge and activity imposes on us. The reality is that,
whatever our intuitions, whatever the pressures on us, we have to
assemble arguments and we have to make judgments that don’t turn out to
be wrong.
This is what assembling
arguments actually looks like, visually conceptualised. This is not simply a
recommendation that we attempt a fancy new method. It is a method based on
what our brains instinctively try to do, but cannot manage beyond a
certain modest point, because of limited working memory and lack of a clear
technique. Because this is what our brains are trying to do -
assemble a representation in visual terms of what the structure of an
argument presented in speech or prose actually is - a technology for doing
it systematically and externally can work.
The practice enters into
the suite of standard practices and modifies them. It no more abolishes
prose than prose abolished speech. Rather, the traditional techniques of
contemplation, research and debate feed into a new approach to drafting,
refining and evaluating argument structure, making possible a whole new
level of clarity in communicating and correcting arguments. This new
approach, argument mapping, offers the possibility of navigating around
arguments with the increased ease and clarity that was offered by Abram
Ortelius’s Theatrum orbis terrarum to those who desired, mentally or
physically, to navigate around the known world.
The technology is, of
course, at an early stage of development. Argument mapping can, in
principle, be done on paper or on a whiteboard, but it quickly becomes messy
and cumbersome using those technologies. This may go far toward explaining
why it was not taken up, or even conceived, until quite recently. The
earliest record of anyone using a graphical device to lay out argument
structure is a footnote to an influential nineteenth century text book on
logic, by one Richard Whately. Some cumbersome efforts were made to pioneer
the technique in legal reasoning a century ago, but it was only with the
advent of reasonably sophisticated information technology and graphical
software, about a decade or so ago, that the technique started to become
feasible on a wider basis.
In reflecting on why this should be so, I
am drawn back to the origins of writing itself. As many of you are doubtless
aware, writing originated, or so the best current research tells us, in
Sumer in the fourth millennium BCE, as city states struggled to deal with
the cognitive burdens entailed in trade and taxation. Writing arose, in
other words, as a thoroughly practical accounting measure, not as a poetic
or literary device. Those things came later. Necessity was the mother of
invention, as the old saying has it. Beyond that initial necessity, however,
the new technology opened up possibilities almost certainly not imagined by
the original utilitarian inventors.
In the present case, the necessity is
generated by the sheer, overwhelming quantities of information and argument
we have to cope with in the early twenty first century. We can no longer
afford the inefficiencies and expenditures of energy entailed in processing
such information and argument by the traditional means. We need - as we are
continually reminded by strategic and intelligence failures in both the
corporate and government worlds - greater transparency in how decisions are
reached and greater clarity in reasoning within decision-making groups.
Argument maps are a means to this end. They
are not proofs of a given proposition, but displays of an argument for a
such a proposition. They are more open to precise, useful correction than is
prose. The better the map, the truer this is. Remember, even the best
geographic maps change, when the facts change. Their truth is not given once
for all. Until 1992, for example, there was no separate Ukraine, Lithuania,
Latvia, Estonia, Khazkhstan, just the Soviet Union, on maps of Eurasia.
Argument maps, too, then, are open to correction. Their clarity of
inferential and evidential structure makes them readily corrigible, but in a
transparent manner, not by the mere accumulation of polemics that all too
often bypass one another in a blizzard of prose.
About four years ago, I read Doug Cocks’
book on the population debate in Australia. Austhink had, at that time, only
just been created. I was interested in the book from a substantive point of
view, but what struck me especially was the all but impenetrable complexity
of its argument. This is not a comment on Doug’s prose, but on the nature of
prose itself and the considerable complexity of the debate he was seeking to
elucidate.
In an effort to clarify what
the balance of claims was in this debate, at least as recorded by Doug, we
created an argument map. I
don’t present it here with any intention of suggesting that it is a complete
representation of the debate or of Doug’s book, but simply as an example of
how even a basic, top-level map, can give us a rapid grasp of both the scope
and balance of claims in a major debate.
Observe that, simply in colour-coded,
structural terms, you can see here that there are five top level claims both
for and against the proposition that Australia should increase its
population. Unlike almost any prose representation that I can think of, this
instantly creates a sense of balance or, if you like, counter-balance, in
the debate, which acts as an automatic corrective to those tendencies I
referred to earlier - confirmation bias and belief preservation - that tend
to skew our attention to and use of evidence in argument.
At least on this representation of the
matter, one can also see, almost instantly, that two of the reasons in
support and one of the reasons against the proposition have been heavily
rebutted, while one of the reasons against has no supporting evidence of any
kind. This is simply a representation of the argument as Doug presented it.
It does not contain any opinion of ours. What it offers, I suggest, is an
access to what the debate actually is, where the balance of considerations
lies, where the boundaries of it lie, that is exceptionally difficult to
gain from simply reading the book.
Is argument mapping difficult? Actually, it
is not. If you are completely clear what your argument is, then mapping it
is a trivial exercise. The difficulty you experience in mapping your
argument is a direct measure of the lack of clarity you have about what your
argument is. Standard cognitive processes enable you, indeed encourage you,
to remain vague about this and to obscure your lack of clarity in prose that
can seem profound because impenetrable.
Argument mapping offers the possibility of
easier and greater comprehension of arguments, increased quality of
arguments, better communication of arguments and more reliable judgments
based on better reasoning. But it is, of course, a skill, like any technical
skill and one that will initially seem foreign and awkward to most of us,
because we are so accustomed to the use of other methods for recording,
analysing and communicating arguments.
Faced with this elementary
cultural reality, I console myself with the remembrance that writing was,
for millennia, an arcane art confined to priests and scribes, while until
even a few years ago the use of email was similarly a rare and unfamiliar
art. We have just begun a process of innovation here and the usual tests of
technological feasibility, cultural acceptability and, overwhelmingly, of
practical utility will determine the path forward. I am just pleased to be
at the edge of innovation and to have the opportunity to share with you a
little of what it is about.
Are there any questions? |